Showing posts with label foundations of economics. Show all posts
Showing posts with label foundations of economics. Show all posts

Sunday, September 23, 2018

Branko Milanovic — 1½ Adam Smiths

The recent book by Jesse Norman simply entitled “Adam Smith” is a pleasure to read. There are of course innumerable books on the founder of the political economy, so why another one? Norman’s book is directed toward that, at times elusive, general educated reader, and has, in my opinion, three objectives: (i) to situate Adam Smith in his time, both intellectually and politically, (ii) to argue that there is a remarkable consistency between the Adam Smith of the Theory of Moral Sentiments, Lectures on Jurisprudence and the Wealth of Nations, and (iii) to show that most of neoclassical and laissez-faire appropriations of Adam Smith are at best one-sided, and in many cases downright wrong....
Global Inequality
1½ Adam Smiths
Branko Milanovic | Visiting Presidential Professor at City University of New York Graduate Center and senior scholar at the Luxembourg Income Study (LIS), and formerly lead economist in the World Bank's research department and senior associate at Carnegie Endowment for International Peace

Thursday, May 24, 2018

J. W. Mason — The Wit and Wisdom of Trygve Haavelmo


More philosophy of economics, or foundations, if you prefer. Good read if you are into this. It runes along the lines of what amateur economist and working physicist Jason Smith has been saying about foundations.

J. W. Mason's Blog
The Wit and Wisdom of Trygve Haavelmo
JW Mason | Assistant Professor of Economics, John Jay College, City University of New York

Monday, April 30, 2018

Jason Smith — The ability to predict


Another good one on foundations of science and economics, specifically macroeconomics — if you are into this sort of thing.
These papers also fail to make any empirical predictions or really engage with data at all. I get the impression that people aren't actually interested in making predictions or an actual scientific approach to macro- or micro-economics, but rather in simply using science as a rhetorical device....
Information Transfer Economics
The ability to predict
Jason Smith

Wednesday, January 17, 2018

Jason Smith — What to theorize when your theory's rejected

I was part of an epic Twitter thread yesterday, initially drawn in to a conversation about whether the word "mainstream" (vs "heterodox") was used in natural sciences (to which I said: not really, but the concept exists). There was one sub-thread that asked a question that is really more a history of science question (I am not a historian of science, so this is my own distillation of others' work as well a couple of my undergrad research papers).
Useful relative to philosophy of science and history of science, as well as foundations of economics. Philosophy of science makes use of the history of science.

It is also relevant to the orthodox and heterodox debate in economics.

Information Transfer Economics
What to theorize when your theory's rejected
Jason Smith

Wednesday, December 13, 2017

Jason Smith — On these 33 theses

The other day, Rethinking Economics and the New Weather Institute published "33 theses" and metaphorically nailed them to the doors of the London School of Economics. They're re-published here. I think the "Protestant Reformation" metaphor they're going for is definitely appropriate: they're aiming to replace "neoclassical economics" — the Roman Catholic dogma in this metaphor — with a a pluralistic set of different dogmas — the various dogmas of the Protestant denominations (Lutheran, Anabaptist, Calvinist, Presbyterian, etc). For example, Thesis 2 says:
2. The distribution of wealth and income are fundamental to economic reality and should be so in economic theory.
This may well be true, but a scientific approach does not assert this and instead collects empirical evidence that we find to be in favor of hypotheses about observables that are affected by the distribution of wealth. A dogmatic approach just assumes this. It is just as dogmatic as neoclassical economics assuming the market distribution is efficient.
In fact, several of the theses are dogmatic assertions of things that either have tenuous empirical evidence in their favor or are simply untested hypotheses. These theses are not things you dogmatically assert, but rather should show with evidence:
I wonder whether economics should be taught as a science, especially since conventional economists seem to think that economics is more like physics than the social sciences.

There are problems with assuming that, which I won't repeat. But to my mind, the most obvious difficulty is well-known among the public. Perhaps the most powerful argument for "science" is demonstrated not in words, or through experiment, but rather in the success of technology that everyone uses all the time to change the world.

Is there anything like this with respect to economics? Not only no, but also the opposite in many cases.

The study economics is not even a required in most business schools, because business schools have discovered that time is better spent in getting results. If it got results, business schools would be hiring the top economists. They are not.

The teaching of economics needs to be rethought in light not only of the failure of economists to deliver results but also in their making bad situations worse. The dismal handling of the aftermath of the global financial crisis is a case in point. In addition, conventional economists and policymakers have literally laid waste entire European countries and their economies.

A lot of people are likely thinking, if this science we want none of it. Monkeys throwing darts could probably do better.

And ironically, Western economists and policymakers were put to shame by the positive result that China showed using a command economy to address the issues promptly and avoid contraction. But Western economists explain this by "cheating."

Information Transfer Economics
Jason Smith

Tuesday, December 12, 2017

Lars P. Syll — On the non-applicability of statistical models


Math is purely formal, involving the relation of signs based on formation and transformation rules. Signs are given significance based on definitions. Math is applicable to the world through science to the degree that the definitions are amenable to measurement and the model assumptions approximate real world conditions (objects in relation to others) and events (patterned changes in these relations). Methodological choices determine the scope and scale of the model, which in turn determines the fitness of formal modeling for explanation of real world conditions and events.

Contemporary science is chiefly about applying formal modeling to theoretical explanation that covers a wide enough range of phenomena worth explaining to be of interest. The scientific project is about designing useful models for explaining phenomena and also designing experiments to test the model against observation. This involves measurement.

A further challenge is identifying parameters that can be measured to produce data and constructing models based on assumptions of how parameters are related with respect to states and how they change over time.

Then, there are also presumptions that are not stated. For example, it is presumed that science is consilient and therefore, any theoretical explanation that violates the conservation laws is ruled out automatically.

Beyond that philosophical foundations relating to metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, social and political philosophy, philosophy of science, the philosophy of the particular discipline, etc., also come into play.

Quite evidently, there is a lot of room for mistake and slip-ups in the process of "doing science."

Formalization and data are not magic wands, and assuming they are leads to magical thinking. Formalization is only rigorous — necessary based on application off rules — with respect to models. How models relate to what is modeled is contingent and depends on data. Data is dependent on observation and measurement.

All this is difficult enough in the natural sciences, but more difficult in the life sciences and much so in the social sciences.

The philosophy of economics, or foundations of economics if one prefers, needs to take all this into consideration and there needs to be lively debate about it. Is there?

Lars P. Syll’s Blog
On the non-applicability of statistical models
Lars P. Syll | Professor, Malmo University

Thursday, October 19, 2017

Jason Smith — In the right frame, economies radically simplify


More thoughts on economic methodology. First a framework is needed and then theories can be constructed and tested in that framework. The simplest frame and most economical theory that explains the data sufficiently to be useful is preferred.

A framework involving complexity is not necessarily better than one that doesn't as long as it gets the job done.

Smith observes that theories constructed within the conventional framework that conventional economists presume is not getting the job of explanation and prediction done very well.

He cautions that this doesn't necessarily mean that a more complex framework is better at explanation (formal theoretical model) and prediction (empirical testing of the model against adequate data).
The dynamic equilibrium frame [of Smith's information transfer economics] not only radically simplifies the description of the data, but radically reduces the information content of the data.... 
This is all to say the dynamic equilibrium model bounds the relevant complexity of macroeconomic models. I've discussed this before here, but that was in the context of a particular effect. The dynamic equilibrium frame bounds the relevant complexity of all possible macroeconomic models. If a model is more complex than the dynamic equilibrium model, then it has to perform better empirically (with a smaller error, or encompass more variables with roughly the same error). More complex models should also reduce to the dynamic equilibrium model in some limit if only because the dynamic equilibrium model describes the data.
This would suggest that the methodological debate in economics is not over, as conventional economists claim.

Information Transfer Economics
In the right frame, economies radically simplify
Jason Smith

Tuesday, September 5, 2017

Lars P. Syll — Methodological arrogance


On reductionism.

This is also the case in philosophy where different methods attempt to exclude other methods by reducing the debate to a lower level of data, e.g, sense data only, or lower order of abstraction, e.g., all abstraction must be reducible to first order. These methodological assumptions reduce justification to observations of objects. For example, David Hume used philosophical reduction to sense data to exclude causality, arguing that causality is nothin more than observation of constant correlation.

The idea is that everything at a higher scale must be accountable at a lower scale. This doesn't even apply in physics (yet) as the hardest science, where the scope of quantum mechanics (micro) and cosmology (macro) still fall outside each other, and questions loom about how to reconcile the micro and macro levels.

To insist on reduction to individual psychology and behavior in economics is indeed arrogant, especially when the social unit in sociology is the family and economic considers economic units in terms of households and firms, and neither human psychology nor behavior are well understood (explained) scientifically.

Reductionism is a methodological assumption that is unsubstantiated by rigorous criteria. It is a stipulation and insisting on it as exclusive is arrogant when there are alternatives in the debate. This is the arrogance of dogmatism rather than open inquiry as the basis of gaining knowledge and the origin of scientific method in an environment where theology reigned.

In short, it is not only arrogance, it is dangerous, as Popper recognized. This is the point of the open society he advocated. Freedom of thought and expression is the basis for inquiry, discovery, and creativity. The discipline of economics risks falling into irrelevance if orthodoxy insists on imposing methodological reductionism as "settled."

Lars P. Syll’s Blog
Methodological arrogance
Lars P. Syll | Professor, Malmo University

Wednesday, August 9, 2017

Brian Romanchuk — Rigour And Macroeconomics

Much of my writing about macroeconomic theory is of the hand-wringing variety: it cannot be "scientific" because (useful) forecasting is essentially impossible to do. This is a negative (non-constructive) argument; but that does not mean that we cannot be rigorous.
As a comment on my previous article ("Science and Economics") André asked, "If we are unable to test macroeconomic theory, how will we know that it works?" If we use a wide definition of "test," we are able to do so. However, this notion of "testing" would probably raise eyebrows among physical scientists, who perhaps assume that "forecasting" and "testing" would be the same thing in this context. It is possible to look at macro in a rigorous way, but we need to drop the embedded assumption that rigorous means the same thing as acting like physicists.
My arguments here should not actually be surprising to economists, as they are effectively a hidden background assumption in their worldview. Instead, this viewpoint is aimed at non-economists who want to treat macroeconomics like other fields of knowledge.
Brian ventures into philosophy of macroeconomics, a subject that most economists avoid, which means that they presuppose the foundations of their discipline, which implies that they impose their view based on hidden assumptions. Foundational studies attempt to clarify these matters.

I think a good approach to scientific rigor comes from Richard Feynman's observation that a key purpose of science as rigorous thinking is to keep from fooling ourselves. See his Cargo Cult Science.

 Generally speaking, these days "scientific" means using a formal model to represent actual change of events over time in accordance with some invariance that allows for prediction and therefore testing hypotheses. The rigor comes from both rigorous thinking provided by format ionization and also from the ability to compare a model with reality in order to determine its degree of representation. since models are simplification, few models will be exact replicas of event. They don't need to be in order to be useful for the purpose constructed.

So the first step is to generate a model based on assumptions. At the macro level such models are usually understood to be explanatory models in the sense of modeling some mechanism or transmission process that captures some useful level of invariance in changing events.

This implies that the properties of models must reflect the actual pattern of changing events.

This enables testing the model against what is modeled through observational checking.

A fundamental assumption is that the future resembles the past in the area of consideration to be able to identify invariance. Analysis of data from observing the past is indicative but not definitive, and all models are contingent on future observations. Science is therefore tentative.

The greater the degree of ergodicity, the more representational models can be. As uncertainly increases, models necessarily become less rigorous in the sense that the assumptions map future events if the reasoning is correct.

In the case of non-ergodicity, no amount of rigor in model construction or reasoning can guarantee that the future will continue to resemble the past in the way that such models suggest.

The greatest degree of rigor is provided by deterministic functions, which necessitates the ability to measure variables. The next degree of rigor is provided by stochastic functions which allows for estimation based on sampling, for example.

Biology accounts for a degree of apparent determinism in human behavior. Custom, habit account and path dependence account for some observed degree of patterned behavior in human affairs, but this tends to be local rather than universal.

However, where radical uncertainty exists, contingent models are needed, including conceptual models that take matters into consideration that are difficult to impossible to model formally. For instance, science is presumed to be consilient, so that assumptions that conflict with other areas are suspect.

Moreover, there is also a tendency to overgeneralize, fit curves, fudge and nudge, and even see faces in clouds. For example, there is a tendency to overgeneralize by projecting oneself and one's in-group on humanity and concluding that local characteristics are universal. This is the basis of much that is assumed about "human nature."

The result has been that in the social science, including economics, a distinction has been drawn between the micro and macro levels of scope and scale. The micro has tended to assume dominance, since the scope and scale permit a greater degree of rigor that is confirmed at least statistically.

Grand theories that explain behavior at the societal level have fallen out of favor because they are difficult to construct formally and also difficult to measure observationally. So the usefulness of such theories questionable and they fall victim to the charge of being speculative rather than scientific.

Grace O. Okafor's "Grand Theories and Their Critiques: From C. Wright Mills to Post Modernism" explores this in the history of sociology. It is not difficult to find parallels in the history of economics. 

Gary Becker's rational choice approach has spread from economics to the other social sciences as a framework for modeling social, political and economic behavior. This has led to criticism from several angles — bounded rationality, cognitive-affective bias, different types of decision making, contextual asymmetries, reflexivity and emergence, and uncertainty, for example.

Bond Economics
Rigour And Macroeconomics
Brian Romanchuk

Wednesday, August 2, 2017

Brian Romanchuk — Science And Economics

I had largely managed to avoid writing about the latest angst in the economics blogosphere regarding mathematics, science, and economics. I am not a fan of mainstream economics, but at the same time, I question some of the broad brush attacks on economics. The quest to pretend that economics can be a science like physics is doomed, and does not take into account the nature of what is being studied.
Bond Economics
Science And Economics
Brian Romanchuk

Thursday, July 27, 2017

Peter Söderbaum — Redefining economics in terms of multidimensional analysis and democracy

A proposed new theoretical perspective starts with a partly different definition of economics:
“Economics is multidimensional management of (limited) resources in a democratic society”
Why “multidimensional” management? Multidimensional goes against the one-dimensional analysis of neoclassical theory and method. “Monetary reductionism” is no longer accepted. The idea that we should put a monetary price on all impacts, ecosystem services included, to make them commensurable and tradeable, is abandoned. Instead impacts of different kinds are kept separate throughout analysis. And non-monetary impacts are viewed as being as “economic” as monetary ones. This may make analysis more complex but also more relevant.…
Bringing trans-disciplinarity, social value, and quality of life into economic thinking at the foundational level.
Why reference to a democratic society? When reading neoclassical introductory textbooks in economics it becomes clear that “democracy” is not a theme taken seriously. These texts rather reflect an emphasis on economists as experts, i.e. a kind of technocracy....
Real-World Economics Review Blog
Redefining economics in terms of multidimensional analysis and democracy
Peter Söderbaum | Professor Emeritus In Ecological Economics,
Mälardalen University, Sweden

Tuesday, July 4, 2017

Barkley Rosser — Comments on Profit and Capital


Summary of the meanings and uses of the terms "capital" and "profit." Barkley Rosser covers a lot of background in a few short paragraphs.

From the logical perspective, the problematic is that "capital" and "profit" are ordinary language terms that are also technically defined differently in various economic and financial accounts. The quest for the "real" meaning as the "essence" denoted by "capital" and "profit" is therefore doomed to failure.  There is no there there.

This is a problem generally in economics and social science. It is very difficult to establish key terms technically in a way that compels general agreement. Therefore, a plethora of competing theories, none of which are able to rule the day since none qualifies as a best explanation in terms of the commonly accepted criteria of 1) consistency/comprehensiveness, 2) correspondence/evidence, 3) usefulness/practicality, and 5) economy/elegance. So it becomes take your pick, or come up with something that purports to be "better."

Angry Bear
Comments on Profit and Capital
J. Barkley Rosser | Professor of Economics and Business Administration James Madison University

Monday, November 28, 2016

Jason Smith — The scope of introductory economics

Basically, economics isn't approached as an empirical theoretical framework with well-defined scope. It is not set up from the beginning to be amenable to experiments that control the scope and produce data (quantitative or qualitative observations) that can be compared with theory. I'll try and show what I mean using introductory level material -- even qualitative.
Information Transfer Economics
The scope of introductory economics
Jason Smith

Sunday, September 4, 2016

Peter Dorman — Internal/External, Validity/Consistency

As every consultant knows, all the mysteries of the universe can be revealed in a two by two matrix. We divide the cases up one way and then some other way. That gives us four cells and vast, remunerable wisdom.
Here is my version for economics. One way of dichotomizing how much faith we should put into hypotheses is between reasoning and evidence. Reasoning is about consistency. An inconsistent argument is at war with itself in some way and should be regarded with suspicion. The other criterion is evidence. Evidence either adds to or detracts from the validity of an argument. Ideally a hypothesis should be strong on both fronts, although we know our powers of formulating and testing hypotheses are incomplete, especially in social sciences like economics. We don’t necessarily rip up and burn theories that have consistency or validity problems, but we take those problems seriously. Or should.
The other dimension is internal/external. Internal means “with respect to this particular empirical study or body of theory” and external “with respect to all the rest of the empirical cases and theory out there”. Each piece of work needs to be judged on its own terms, but research and analysis do not occur in a vacuum. We also have to be mindful of the empirical world outside our particular sample, and we should respect the models developed by other researchers, especially when they have done well on consistency and validity tests.…
Econospeak
Internal/External, Validity/Consistency
Peter Dorman | Professor of Political Economy, The Evergreen State College

Thursday, September 1, 2016

Jon Hellevig — The Scientific Essence of Economy – Capitalism and Socialism versus a Democratic Competitive Market Economy


Must-read if you are into foundations of economic and political theory. Useful even if you are not, since Jon Hellevig debunks a lot of the myths about capitalism, neoliberalism, liberalism, socialism and communism in advancing his argument for a democratic competitive economy.

Keeper.

Awara Blog
The Scientific Essence of Economy – Capitalism and Socialism versus a Democratic Competitive Market Economy
Jon Hellevig

Sunday, August 21, 2016

Ari Andricopoulos — On Maths and Models

Every now and then a debate seems to flare up about economic models. A recent one started with Noah Smith arguing (in reply to Frances Coppola), that heterodox economics does not have the tools to replace mainstream economics. Steve Keen gave an excellent point by point reply about the mathematical quality of heterodox work. Then Frances also wrote a reply and then another, which  I agree with, pointing out that an understanding of the economy does not require maths. Where maths can be used to formalise this understanding, it is very useful. But economics is not a mathematical equation.
I say this from the point of view of someone with a PhD in mathematics, but whose job is to predict the behaviour of systems, specifically financial systems. And I know that in describing a system, parsimony is king. One should use as much maths as is necessary and not a bit more. The more complex the maths, generally the worse the predictive power.
The economy is a very complex system. It is non-linear with a huge number of unknowns. For this reason prediction is difficult. This seems to have meant that any degree of poor prediction is excused on the grounds that no-one can predict the future. I recommend everyone read this excellent Noah Smith blog post from 2013 which was only let down by the somewhat cowardly conclusion.  It shows DSGE models are not useful as predictions - he points to this paper showing that DSGE models are no better than simple univariate autoregression (AR) models at predicting inflation and GDP growth. Bearing in mind AR models are just simple mean reversion models this is a pretty categorical failure. He then argues that they are neither good for policy advice nor even for communication of ideas, before concluding that we should continue with them as the are the 'only game in town'.
Saying that the economy can't be predicted because it is too complex and no-one knows the future is a big cop out for me. No-one could have predicted with any degree of certainty that the global financial crisis would happen in 2008. This is because it is impossible to predict the timing of events of this nature that depend on triggers and positive feedback loops. It also depends on policy reaction. For example, a possible crash in China early this year was averted by a large government spending programme. But what heteredox economics has done is give keys to understanding the nature of the economy.…
Notes on the Next Bust
On Maths and Models
Ari Andricopoulos | Partner at Dacharan Advisory, Zurich, and PhD in Mathematics

Lars P. Syll — Steve Keen, Noah Smith and heterodox ‘anti-math’ economics

Responding to the critique of his Bloomberg View post on heterodox economics and its alleged anti-math position, Noah Smith approvingly cites Steve Keen telling us there is
a wing of heterodox economics that is anti-mathematical. Known as “Critical Realism” and centred on the work of Tony Lawson at Cambridge UK, it attributes the failings of economics to the use of mathematics itself…
Although yours truly appreciate much of Steve Keen’s debunking of mainstream economics, on this issue he is, however, just plain wrong! For a more truthful characterization of Tony Lawson’s position, here’s what Axel Leijonhufvud has to say:
Lars P. Syll’s Blog
Steve Keen, Noah Smith and heterodox ‘anti-math’ economics
Lars P. Syll | Professor, Malmo University

Wednesday, June 22, 2016