Showing posts with label economics as a science. Show all posts
Showing posts with label economics as a science. Show all posts

Thursday, October 8, 2015

Scientific American — Nobel Laureate Harry Kroto: The Threatened Enlightenment


Relevant to the recent study showing that the majority of peer reviewed economics papers in prestige journals cannot be replicated.
Harry Kroto (Nobel Laureate in Chemistry 1996): I'm gonna talk about what science is because it's a totally misunderstood sort of subject. There are aspects of science which are important and of course we know, the body of knowledge that you learn at school, all right?
The applications of those knowledge - technology, the only thing that journalists ever ask a general 99 percent of the time. Perhaps most important is the way that we discover new knowledge. But for me, the most important, by far, is that it's the only philosophical construct we have to determine truth with any degree of reliability.

Everyone should think about that. Because then it becomes a much bigger subject. In fact, for me, perhaps the most important subject there is. And the ethical purpose of education must involve teaching children how they can decide what they're being told is actually true. And that's not the case in general.

The teaching of a skeptical, evidence-based assessment of all claims - all claims - without exception is fundamentally an intellectual integrity issue. Without evidence, anything goes. Think about it. Common sense says the sun goes round the Earth. Who agrees with me?
Look at it. Starts over here, ends over there. It's uncommon sense that was needed to recognize that the Earth was turning on its axis. The uncommon sense of Copernicus, Galileo, Gendona, Bruna was burnt to death. We had to learn to be very careful and question everything.

Let me just check - how many of you know the evidence for Galileo to say that the Earth was going around the sun? Put your hand up. You've accepted it. Almost nobody's put their hand up. It's incredible.
Look at yourself. You've accepted this. You've accepted a lot of things without evidence. Find out what the evidence is for that. Find out what the evidence is for everything that you accept. 
And the pragmatic criterion clearly doesn't apply in the case of economics and policy.

Scientific American (July 25, 2013)
Nobel Laureate Harry Kroto: The Threatened Enlightenment
Steve Mirsky

Monday, April 6, 2015

Lars P. Syll — Modern macroeconomics – an intellectually lazy ideology


Apt quote from Diane Coyle, who makes the point that a model is just a model and as such it is dependent on the assumptions used to construct it. But the quote doesn't go far enough.

Issues other than formal consistency arise when a model is interpreted semantically with respect to the world it models when that world is assumed to be real and therefore experience becomes a test of the semantic interpretation of the model. All models are necessarily simplifications. Replicas to scale are highly isomorphic representations, but differ in size from what they model.

But most models are more abstract. Their representational power lies in their isomorphism with what is modeled, but the degree of correspondence is much less exactly than replicas. Often this is not an issue, since either a higher degree is not required of the model with respect to its purpose, or the subject matter doesn't permit it. This is accomplished by loosening the assumptions.

The greater the abstraction, the more questions arise about how much weight assumptions are being asked to bear, and if they are being pushed too far.
Although we all knew at some level that the rational choice assumption was being made to bear too much weight, very few economists openly challenged its everyday use in justifying public policy decisions. Very few of us put this weight on it in our own work. But not all that many economists challenged its pervasive use in the public policy world…
Well, now we know how that turned out, and it is not over even yet — over seven years later, with untold consequences, socially, politically, financially, and economically.

This is comparable to using wrong assumptions in engineering in building or bridge construction, or designing dams, bulwarks or levies, with the consequence that the structure collapses owing to unplanned for stress resulting in huge loss of life and property, and a setback in the area lasting years.

When a model is interpreted semantically as representative of a world, its isomorphism can only be decided based on comparing aspects of the model (hypotheses derived from it as theorems) to what it purports to model, based on experience. This is to say that no amount of analysis of a model that is claimed to be representational can justify the reliability of the model as a representational one. For that, comparing the model to what is modeled is required. Much of the scientific method is about doing this rigorously.

Of course, it is also a requisite that modeling be formally consistent, but formal consistency implies nothing about what's outside the symbolism of the model. Formal consistency implies that if the logic, and math is a brach of logic, is valid and the premises are correct, then the theorems that follow are true as hypotheses in a semantic interpretation. But this is no guaranteed of the truth of the hypotheses semantically. It is just an assertion that follows from the logic. It is claim that stands in need of testing. A logical pedigree is never an empirical warrant independently.

However, this is not the end of it. If it were, then a failure of the model could be passed off inadvertent, with the excuse that no one could have known before testing, or that conditions were more severe than could reasonably be expected. No fault. No blame.

But that is a often a bogus excuse. Analysis can reveal likely weak points in a  model where the assumptions are being relied on to bear too much stress, just like in engineering. Engineers don't have to build a bridge to test it, for example. They use design principles that have already been found reliable for good reasons. In most cases, this is trivial where conditions are well-known and the capability of materials and procedure is well established. But in many cases, there is ambiguity or even the presence of unknowns, for example in putting a person on the surface of the moon for the first time. Clearly, those involved, the engineers especially, were not cavalier about this.

In economics, however, this doesn't seem to be the case, where being cavalier — appearing certain in the face of uncertainty — is expected of Very Serious People. Worse, non-economists have not only noticed weak assumptions, but warned in cases where economists were putting too much weight on assumptions in model construction, not only from common experience and common sense, which might be suspect, but also from work in related sciences such as psychology and sociology. Where the FBI saw massive fraud taking place in the real estate bubble as it was building, Alan Greenspan, the nation's "chief economist," saw "froth," assuming that financial experts, corporate management, and the market itself know better.

This failure would just be embarrassing to the field if macroeconomics were not used as a policy science and relied on extensively in policy formulation. Then mistakes become disastrous, and they may even led to catastrophes resulting in huge losses that can never be recaptured, or lives that can never be set right. It's grossly irresponsible — not to mention highly inefficient, when economics is supposed to assist individuals, firms and societies in avoiding or at least reducing inefficiency, vitiating a chief purpose of the discipline.

The financial crisis followed by the non-recovery, as well as the crisis in Euroland, should have put economists on alert to recheck their assumptions and those in charge of policy formulation and financial regulation to review their assumptions also. Instead, many have just doubled down. Science or ideology? Whatever, it's more than laziness.

Lars P. Syll’s Blog
Modern macroeconomics — an intellectually lazy ideologyLars P. Syll | Professor, Malmo University

Monday, January 26, 2015

Lars P. Syll — NAIRU — more religion than science



Lars P. Syll’s Blog
NAIRU — more religion than science
Lars P. Syll | Professor, Malmo University

The reasons for the opposition of the 'industrial leaders' to full employment achieved by government spending may be subdivided into three categories: (i) dislike of government interference in the problem of employment as such; (ii) dislike of the direction of government spending (public investment and subsidizing consumption); (iii) dislike of the social and political changes resulting from the maintenance of full employment. We shall examine each of these three categories of objections to the government expansion policy in detail.

Friday, December 5, 2014

Geoff Davies — Reforming economics: pluralism is not enough


Best proposal for reforming the study and teaching of economics that I have encountered. Includes MMT. A must-read. Geoff Davies is an earth scientist rather than an economist, but he as a firm grasp on econ as well as scientific method.

Real-World Economics Review Blog
Reforming economics: pluralism is not enough
Geoff Davies

Monday, September 29, 2014

Adam Ozimek — Enough Already With The Sweeping Claims That Economics Is Unscientific


Ozimek asks the right question, Is economics scientific?, rather than is economics a science? It is possible for a discipline to be scientific without being a science like physics and biology with a well-developed generally agreed upon paradigm that defines normal science in the discipline. This is not the case with psychology or the social sciences, however, where there is no normal paradigm. This does not preclude using scientific method to do research, however. These disciplines are scientific but without being sciences in the sense of having a normal paradigm that defines the existing state of the discipline. 

Orthodox economists have done their best to establish the neoclassic ally based paradigm as the norm for doing economics science. However, there are too many working out of heterodox paradigms to support that claim, especially in light of heterodox successes and criticism of orthodox methodology.

Moreover, there are no overarching criteria that delimit scientific method and determine what is correctly called "scientific" rather than rigorous. "Science" and "scientific" connote "true knowledge" in the ancient sense of episteme (knowledge) versus doxa (opinion) or pistis (conviction or belief). This involves establishing criteria for distinguishing among them, and debate over this has been raging for millennia. The jury is still out.

Much of the controversy is over representation and therefore, misrepresentation. Orthodoxy in whatever field has represented itself as the owner of the true knowledge — "The ocean is in my bucket" — while heterodoxy has disputed that claim as baseless and biased, holding that it rests on an argument from authority based on a good deal of sophistry and reliance on power. These are attributes of dogmatism that rather science.

A fundamental feature of scientific method is that assumptions, hypotheses and conclusions are always tentative. Theories may be very robust based on criteria of consistency, correspondence, pragmatism, and elegance, but a theory is never timeless true and beyond question, revision, or even replacement by a new paradigm.

Forbes — Modeled Behavior
Enough Already With The Sweeping Claims That Economics Is Unscientific
Adam Ozimek | economist at Moody's Analytics
h/t Mark Thoma at Economist's View

Tuesday, March 11, 2014

Geoff Davies — A Science of Economies?


Can economics be a science. Yes, according to Davies, but it requires sacking the economists for people that understand doing real science instead of playing at it.

Real-World Economics Review Blog
A Science of Economies?
Geoff Davies

Davies is an Earth scientist interested in economics. He is the author of Sack the Economists.